Soziale Systeme 3 (1997), H.2, S. 219-235
Religion, residual problems, and functional differentiation: an
ambiguous relationship
Peter Beyer
Zusammenfassung: Der Artikel untersucht am Beispiel der modernen
Religionen die fast paradoxe Beziehung zwischen Ausdifferenzierung
(Systembildung) und Entdifferenzierung in der funktional differenzierten
Weltgesellschaft. Die Kritik der Religionen an den typischen Folgeproblemen
dieser Gesellschaft ist symptomatisch dafür, daß gerade in diesem
Bereich eine Spannung herrscht zwischen Systembildung und Anti-
oder Nicht-Systembildung. Die Religion besitzt eine Art "Wahlverwandtschaft"
mit den Folgeproblemen der modernen Gesellschaft, und zwar aus zwei
Gründen. Zum einen finden diese Probleme einen Widerhall in den
Schwierigkeiten, Religion als ein funktionales System unter anderen
zu konstruieren, und zum andern wegen der holistischen Perspektive
der differenzierten Religion überhaupt. Die Probleme, die uns als
charakteristische Folgen der Dominanz spezialisierter Technik erscheinen,
verweisen auf die Ambivalenz, die sich aus der Umstrukturierung
der Religion in eine spezialisierte Technik ergeben, und auf die
Schwierigkeit, in der heutigen Gesellschaft diese Folgeprobleme
auf einer anderen Basis als der technisch-funktionalen zu bewältigen.
I
World society today has, as its dominant structural form, the functional
differentiation of its major subsystems. Most observers of global
social reality would not state the matter in quite such Luhmannian
terms; but notions which speak about the ascendancy of capitalism,
a global state system, or simply technical rationality implicitly
point in the same direction. Current discussions about globalization
in fact show a prevalence of economic and political conceptions
(for example, Shaw 1994; Thomas
et al. 1987; Wallerstein
1995; cf. Waters 1995), with
the addition of, broadly speaking, cultural perspectives that almost
invariably assume a background of states, economy, and technique
(Beck 1986; Featherstone
1995; Giddens 1990; Robertson
1992). These approaches continue and expand under the titles
of globalization and its cognates what a vast social-scientific
and philosophical tradition has analyzed as geographically more
restricted and often state-centred modern societies.
One of the more striking features of quite a few of both the current
and past efforts at describing modern and now global society is
the degree to which these focus on what they deem to be negative
results of the modernization and the globalization process (cf.
Luhmann 1984; 1987a),
on what I wish to call its residual problems. Such critique varies
a great deal, both in content and severity. Yet among the concerns
expressed in more recent theories, certain ones recur consistently
and stand out as primary: globalization leads to the oppression
of the majority of people by a minority (Holm/Sensen
1995; Wallerstein 1979);
it homogenizes and restricts the possibilities for individual and
collective human action in favour of the technically rational, the
superficial, and even the "inhuman" (Bauman
1989; Ellul 1954; Ritzer 1996;
Saul 1992); it destroys the physical
and biological environment to the general detriment of life on earth
(Rifkin 1991; Gordon/Suzuki
1991); and it addicts us to the futile quest for more and more
control that also yields permanent crisis and constant insecurity
(Beck 1986).
A remarkable feature of these critiques is that they accuse modern
and global society of negating precisely those values that are actually
most typical of it, ideals such as equality, freedom, tolerance,
and progress. Underdevelopment, racism, sexism, the "iron cage",
dependency, alienation, risk, imperialism, environmental degradation,
totalitarianism, among other terms, all pass moral judgements on
the basis of these motive forces, these characteristic ideals of
the largest part of contemporary society. The critiques, therefore,
are largely not those of an alternative vision let alone a rising
class, like a liberal bourgeois critique of an aristocratic society.
Rather, like romanticism, they correspond to bourgeois or modern
society itself: they assume functionally differentiated society
and espouse its characteristic values, even if they take the form
of seemingly anti-systemic counter-images. What this means is that
they do not point beyond themselves to a different form of dominant
differentiation. At best, like the early Marx, they envision a society
without differentiation or only segmentary differentiation; and
these possibilities they leave in an evocative mist sometimes nostalgically
described as "community" (cf. Morris
1996). To the degree that any solutions are even possible on
the basis of such critiques, either they amount to a straightforward
negation and refusal; or, much more typically, they end up resorting
to those functionally systemic techniques that are at the root of
the problems, especially the legal and the political.
My purpose in this article, however, is not to critique the critiques;
nor is it to deny the problems attendant upon technically rational
dominance. Rather I look more closely at the almost paradoxical
relation between systemicity and anti-systemicity in global, functionally
differentiated society. More specifically, I examine how contemporary
religion points to and illustrates this ambiguity; how religious
response to the characteristic problems of this society is itself
symptomatic of a more general struggle within the religious sphere
between systemicity and non-systemicity or anti-systemicity.(1)
Religion, more than other domains of functional specialization (with
the possible exception of art), has a kind of "elective affinity"
with the residual problems of modern society because they resonate
with the difficulties attendant upon constructing religion as a
function system in the social context of a dominance of functional
differentiation. The problems that appear to us to be the result
of a dominance of specialized technique point to the ambivalence
attendant upon forming religion as one specialized technique beside
others.
Associating religion with non-technical, non-instrumental, or at
least a different kind of reason is not particularly recent, especially
in the Western cultural spheres of Judaism, Christianity, and Islam.
From Augustine to al-Ghazali to Maimonides, the question of the
relation between "reason" and "revelation" has
for some centuries been an important moment in the differentiation
of religion in these areas, especially in Western European society.
In recent times, however, the dominance of non-religious (that is,
secularized) instrumental systems has led various religious observers
to insist on a more radical difference between religion and other
social forms. These efforts have often implied the de-differentiation
of religion: religion is said to distinguish itself as that which
cannot be differentiated. I refer, therefore, not to 19th century
critiques of religion as irrational, illusory, or inferior; but
to religious protests that reject the relegation of religion to
one functional domain beside other, autonomous ones. Included under
this heading would be the Syllabus of Errors of Pope Pius IX; declarations
of such varied people as Swami Vivekananda, Angarika Dharmapala,
and Liang Shu-ming that Hinduism, Buddhism, or Confucianism offer
a necessary "spiritual" corrective to the "one-sided
materialism" (read: technical dominance) of the West; the opposition
of genuine "faith" to degenerated "religion"
by such varied Christian thinkers as Jacques Ellul, Dietrich Bonhoeffer,
and Wilfrid Cantwell Smith; and the assertions by numerous Muslims,
Hindus, Buddhists, Jews, and representatives of aboriginal religions
that theirs is not a religion, but a (holistic) "way of life".
In each of these cases, the basis of the protest is that we cannot
and should not "reduce" religion to one (technical) domain
beside others. What is at issue is the incorporation of religion
into the logic of functional differentiation.
Religion, therefore, from these perspectives, offers an approach
to the world that is much more than one specialized technique beside
others. It represents not just another possibility, but the foundation
of all possibilities. Religion, we are given to understand, is about
the whole, about what makes the possible possible; and therefore
cannot be compartmentalized. As a by now century long sociological
tradition has argued, what we now call religion does seem to have
some such foundational qualities. The question of religions
general character, however, can only make sense in a particular
social context in which we try to express that character. In the
case of modern and by now global society, the dominance of functionally
differentiated systems means that the social reality of religion
as an autonomous modality of communication will depend significantly
on how well we can imagine and reconstruct religion in the form
of a function system. And this, in turn, depends on how well such
a system can accommodate the holistic character of religion
its claim to provide access to the holistic foundations of reality
in the sort of technical, specialized, and in this sense
partial form that these systems typically have developed in global
society. The protests just mentioned point to a definite problem
in this regard.
If we accept this diagnosis, then those same religious objections
will also provide a fertile perspective from which to criticize
functionally differentiated society as such, especially as manifest
in its historically typical residual problems. As the consequences
of functional differentiation, these can be treated as symptoms
of religious failings. One possible formulation might run like this:
by not giving religion its place, we are seduced to instrumental
hubris and thus, to our peril, lose sight of the insufficiency of
human endeavour and its need to be grounded in something beyond
itself.
We can look at this challenge to religion in a slightly different
way in order to highlight how the problem for religion is at the
same time one for functionally differentiated society as such. Religiousness
is in modern and global circumstances under contextual pressure
to form itself selectively as another instrumental system, which
means as another technically rational system that focuses on the
reproduction and increase of its characteristic communication. Among
the essential symptoms of such systematization would be convergent
centres of religious authority, expressly religious organizations
(many with global extent or at least more than local range), articulated
religious programmes elaborating clear religious binary codes, and
the effective (self-) observation of these institutions explicitly
as religion.(2)
Such systematization is by no means some sort of evolutionary necessity.
Modern and global society could probably manage without a religious
system, although that would not mean the elimination of religious
communication. To the extent that religion does form as a system,
however, it will present no better possibilities for addressing
the typical residual problems of functionally differentiated society
than other systems. For, if the dominance of functional differentiation
is itself at the root of problems like inequality, insecurity, and
environmental degradation; then functionally specialized religion
will be just as susceptible as other, more powerful systems such
as economy and science to being seen as part of the problem, not
just as the source of solutions. And indeed, it is not unusual to
hear religious critics of modern and global society target not just
imperialists, capitalists, and technocrats, but also "conservative"
religion and religious authorities.(3)
To cite just two examples, Latin American liberationists have thus
criticized Roman church authorities and burgeoning Pentecostalism
for reinforcing the status quo; while Ali Shariati and his followers
in pre-revolutionary Iran condemned "Safavid" ulama for
being quiescent and thus aiding and abetting injustice (cf. Beyer
1994).
This said, the alternative for religion and its carriers is to
avoid functionally specific systemization, to avoid extensive organization,
orthodoxifications, and self-presentation as religion. We see evidence
of such a desideratum in various religious manifestations like Western
neo-paganism, New Age movements, and, ironically enough, Pentecostalism.
All three of these eschew convergent systematization in principle,
if not actually in practice. This direction, however, risks precisely
the "invisibility" of religion which, as Luckmann (1963)
notes, amounts to fairly radical secularization. A sort of middle
ground offers itself in the form of the social (religious) movement;
but this type of social system, although potentially quite effective
for mobilizing religious resources toward specific problems, suffers
from the disadvantage, like Webers charisma, of being inherently
evanescent. Sooner or later, social movements have to transform
into something else, or disappear. In consequence, we are likely
to continue to witness religion expressing itself in all these possibilities:
in a function system, in social movements, and in non-systemic forms.
The latter two, at least, usually with a strong element of protest,
of opposition to the dominant social structures, albeit very often
in the name of the dominant value-orientations of global society
and only sometimes against them.
These rather extended introductory remarks now require further
elaboration. The remainder of this essay thus takes a few steps
back to examine various key questions that the foregoing observations
imply. Specifically, I look at aspects of the history of the functional
differentiation of religion under modernizing and globalizing conditions.
Questions of binary codings and the relation of religion to other
instrumental systems are part of a presentation that seeks to isolate
the specific character and peculiar problems of religion in modern
society. On this basis, I then return to the question of how religion
relates to the typical residual problems of global society.

II
Niklas Luhmanns work on religion gives several useful starting
points for a closer analysis of what religion has become in the
modern era, and some of the consequences of these transformations.(4)
Particularly fruitful is the idea of looking at the more recent
history of religion precisely in terms of its functional differentiation;
and, in that context, comparing the structures of the religious
system to those of other function systems. The differentiation in
the context of comparison is, of course, more than a question of
scientific observation; it places the emphasis on religions
position as one function system beside others, not merely on the
possibilities for religious differentiation as such.
A discussion of the place of religion in modern and global society
cannot confine itself to a discussion of Christianity; but for historical
reasons, any analysis has to begin here. Following Luhmanns
analysis, but making various additions and emendations, the story
begins effectively in Western Europe during the Middle Ages. In
the wake of the gradually disappearing Roman world, the Christian
church emerged for some time as the only overarching institution
of the region, representing not only differentiated religion, but
also preserving and carrying forward important portions of Greco-Roman
culture that would later play a role in the emergence of a functionally
differentiated society. The church was a religious institution with
multifunctional characteristics. In the context of a society in
which stratified differentiation dominated and no overpowering traditional
political empire emerged, the church became the expression of a
functional religious system of probably unparalleled contrast with
the surrounding society.
By the High Middle Ages, we can justifiably speak of an "age
of faith", not because Europeans were so exceptionally pious,
but because the religious system through the church and its professional,
often monastic, representatives was so prominent. The medieval "explosion
of sin" in the context of a "scarcity of salvation"
documented by Delumeau (1983;
cf. Luhmann 1989) was the
obverse face of an exceptional increase in the pastoral techniques
and resources whose purpose was to deal with these problems. The
church had other important roles beside the religious, yet at the
core of all these endeavours was the pursuit of faith, the increase
and elaboration of religious communication and religious consciousness.
Two aspects of this medieval European story are of particular importance
for our purposes here. First is that reflexivity and closure of
this religious system centred around the two binary codes of salvation/damnation
and the moral good/bad (Luhmann
1987b; 1989). People engaged
in religious activity for the sake of salvation, a scarce quality
which it was impossible to attain without the help of the churchs
resources because of the severity of sin, that is, human moral weakness.
An elaborated and, from the perspective of the religious system,
unified moral code connected virtually all human social activity
to the quest for salvation and the real possibility of damnation.
In a society where stratified differentiation dominated and so much
of the most important communication happened in face-to-face interactions,
moral coding could and did provide a solid connection between differentiated
religious concerns and the rest of social life. Second, with the
addition of its, strictly speaking, non-religious functions, the
church, as the institutional incarnation of the religious system,
was not only a very salient and powerful presence in this society.
As far as functionally specialized institutions were concerned,
it had for a time no real competitors. Other functional institutions,
notably the political, were comparatively weak. In retrospect, we
can see that the almost hyper-development of the religious system
in the absence of the serious political counterweight that characterized
most other civilizations with differentiated religion was one of
the prime conditions for the eventual shift to a dominance of functional
differentiation in Western society. That transformation, once it
was seriously under way in the later medieval period, led to the
further differentiation of the religious system, but now increasingly
in a context of competition from other rising function systems,
above all the political/legal, the economic, and the scientific;
and also eventually, perhaps even more critically, the health, the
educational, the artistic, and that for mass information media.
In these circumstances, religion fared reasonably well for quite
some time. The comparative weaknesses that it showed after the 18th
century have to be seen against the background of its previous exceptional
prominence and of the greater capacity for instrumental specialization
of at least some of its systemic competitors. To a certain extent,
religion weakened in the West because it had once been so strong;
but only to a certain extent.
The Reformation and its aftermath illustrate some of the key dynamics
involved. The root impulse of most reformers was to purify religion,
which would seem to mean to enhance its differentiation. Yet what
they reacted against was the instrumentality of the church, its
elaborate technicization as a specialized institution centred around
the salvation/ damnation code. Less directly at issue, but also
of importance, was the multifunctionality of the church, its wealth,
its political power especially. At least for the dominant Lutheran,
Calvinist, and Zwinglian movements, the solution, as Luhmann points
out (1989), was to insert
grace as a code in between salvation/damnation and good/bad. This
emphasis on "faith" rather than "works" tended
to differentiate religion even more from other domains of human
activity. It aimed at increasing the recursiveness of religious
communication, so that only "religious" criteria would
be relevant. The resulting devaluation of any technical means to
gain salvation, however, points to the tendency of highly differentiated
religion to disconnect from "worldly" or "profane"
social life. Unlike the today more dominant functional domains such
as law, politics, economy, science, and health; but like art, religion,
it would seem, becomes less instrumental at high levels of differentiation.
This difference is borne out in other religions as well, such as
in the Zen notion of "sudden" enlightenment and the Daoist
idea of non-action. In general, it seems that pure religion tends
toward "other-worldliness" at the level of its more primary
codings, making secondary codings such as a moral code all the more
important if religion is to have direct social relevance.
In the Protestant case, the "faith only" or radical predestinarian
directions were never successfully pursued: they would have subjectivized
the code too much or simply put it beyond human disposition. Instead,
we see a rather rapid return to some form of ecclesiastical and
ritual instrumentalization and to a continuing emphasis on morality
for connecting the possibility of salvation or damnation to life
"in the world". Justification by faith, no less than Catholic
sacramental mediation of grace, needed to find a way of reconnecting
to other social systems of meaning. The moral code was and remains
even today the dominant way of doing this, at least in Christianity.
That dependency, however, also points to certain important disadvantages
for this religion in the modernizing context.
As long as morality occupied a relatively central and unifying
role within European society, respecifying the religious code through
a moral code could be and was quite effective. With the rise of
other function systems and the decline of the more morally dependent
stratified systems, however, morality gradually lost that centrality.
The different rising systems generated their own independent, different,
and not infrequently, from the perspective of the prevailing religio-moral
code, immoral criteria for action. As these became more dominant,
morality became one regulator of social action beside other more
and more prevalent considerations of functional or technical efficacy.
Moreover, given that religion was itself a highly developed function
system with its own "raison déglise", it could also
become the subject of moral evaluation and critique (cf. Luhmann
1989, 307). Here we have at least one of the reasons that contemporary
religious criticism of functional differentiation and its consequences
will tend to include criticism of religion to the extent that it
presents itself as just another functionally specialized institution.
The decentralization or deprivileging of morality because of the
rise of other function systems not dependent on moral regulation
did not, however, mean that moral questions were no longer important.
Far from it. What it did mean was that religion, as one function
system beside others, could no longer as self-evidently claim moral
questions as its own; and that moral considerations were, from the
perspective of society as a whole, less determinative.
Another critical aspect of these transformations for which the
Reformation and its aftermath provide good illustration concerns
the pluralization of religion into religions. Here the rapidly rising
prominence of the political system of states played a key role.
The confessional splits that resulted from the Reformation expressed
religious differences, but these would in all likelihood not have
broken the organizational and theological unity of the Western Christian
church if rising political powers had not used the opportunity to
free themselves more effectively from ecclesiastical tutelage. The
Westphalian formula tended to identify states with either the Catholic
or one of the Protestant churches. But far from being simply a reformulation
along national lines of what had existed before across state boundaries
before, it expressed rather the superiority of political over religious
power. The English Reformation is the clearest example, but the
situation was not that much different even in Catholic countries.
It is in this context of rough and temporary coordination of political
and religious boundaries that we see arise conceptualizations of
religion and religions that parallel the distinctions between the
state and states or, eventually, nations. Much as the state became
a common political form which could only exist concretely as a plurality
of states, so European observers, beginning in the 17th century,
began to treat religion as a generic form for which there were a
plurality of concrete manifestations: not simply Protestantism and
Catholicism, for these were versions of Christianity; but, in the
light of the beginning parallel expansion of European power to all
corners of the world, also other religions, initially Islam, Judaism,
and "paganism"; and then in the 18th and 19th centuries,
the other "world religions" (see Almond
1988; Harrison 1990; Marshall
1970; Smith 1964). It must be
stressed, however, that what we do not have here is a sort of ecumenic
discovery and tolerance of religious diversity; that would in all
likelihood have discouraged the new notions because it would encourage
a blurring of boundaries. Rather European religious conflict, predicated
on an intolerant exclusivism and on political and economic competition
between states, was a condition for the possibility of seeing religions
as discrete and more or less mutually exclusive systems of belief
and practice.
This pluralization did not remain at the level of (European) observers
suggestions. The modelling of religions that emerged was approximately
parallel to that of the emerging nations in the sense that there
has been a tendency to see and organize religions as aspects of
national cultures. And we can see that the global imagining and
reconstruction of these religions has very often been closely associated
with the emergence of nationalisms. Yet religion in the West was
not just an undifferentiated aspect of culture or society. It was
also, and more importantly, a differentiated function system. As
Westerners effectively spread the other function systems to the
rest of the world, they tried to do this with religion as well;
not only in the sense of spreading Christianity, but also in the
sense of encouraging other people to reimagine and reconstruct their
religious traditions as religions. Both efforts achieved a modest
amount of success. Nonetheless, the spread and appropriation by
non-Westerners of the model of the nation and the political system
of the modern state has been far less problematic than has been
the spread and appropriation of the model of religion. The reasons
for this difference bring us back to the internal recursive structures
of functionally specialized religion more generally, and once again
to the context of a dominance of functionally differentiation. The
particular pattern that the West followed turns out to have more
general application.
When discussing the binary code of religion more generally, Luhmann
consistently favours the distinction between transcendent and immanent
(e.g. Luhmann 1986, 183-192;
1989; 1991). As an overall
observation about religion, this is a defensible description, even
if no religions actually operate with this code directly. Its usefulness
in the present context is that it points to the holism of religion.
Various sociological definitions of religion try to focus on the
same feature with words like supra-empirical and ultimate. Luhmann
himself puts it in terms of the meaning of meaning (1996).
What is at issue is the aim of religion to structure its communication
in terms of some sort of final ground for the possibility of anything:
how is the possible possible?
This root form of religion has consequences, especially in functionally
differentiated society. The more "pure" religious determinations
are, the less they will be connected to "phenomenal" reality:
the Protestant Reformers could not insist on "faith alone".
The high gods of many small-scale societies are too remote to concern
themselves much with human affairs, but they are responsible for
the fact that anything exists at all. Ultimately, even nirvana has
no own-being and therefore one can say neither that it is nor that
it is not, nor both, and so forth. Put in terms of the transcendent/immanent
code, religion can and at times does strive toward the singularity
of the transcendent (the sacred as Otto (1936)
and Eliade (1959) put it) to escape
the limitations of the polarity.(5)
In light of this feature, highly differentiated religion, not just
in the modern West, will constantly have to face the problem of
respecifying itself into more "compromising" terms. Religion
may be that which deals with the whole, but that, to use a typically
Luhmannian formulation, is an identity that must become a difference
in order to make a difference. Yet such compromise, such distinction
is not restricted by anything inherently religious; it can happen
in an almost infinite variety of ways. As Durkheim (1937)
pointed out, any thing can be sacred because the sacred cannot be
anything in particular. Religion, especially in its differentiated
forms, is therefore susceptible at least as much to pluralization
as to convergence, and this not just accidentally. In a Hindu formulation,
Brahman is singular, but then again there are also 330 million deities.
There are, of course, ways of controlling this pluralization, but
these all involve reconnection to and involvement in, functionally
speaking, non-religious social structures. The consequences of holism
will accordingly depend on the socio-structural context of religion.
In societal situations where functional differentiation does not
dominate, the flexibility that the holistic penchant of religion
implies can and has been an advantage: religion and religious specialists,
as an expression of their concern with religious questions, could
fulfil all sorts of non-religious functions in the name of religion.
We saw a very clear example of this in the above discussion of the
European Middle Ages. When various other function systems rise to
prominence, however, the challenge for religion is that most of
the more powerful ways of reconnecting will become the specializations
of the other systems. Technical specialization leads to the elaboration
of highly improbable but empirically very effective means. Religious
specialists, with their focus on the transcendent as ground of the
immanent, are thereby not specialists in immanent, empirically effective
means. At best, their efforts in this direction will appear supplemental,
to be used in addition or when all else fails: If I am sick, I will
go to a doctor; I may also pray. If threatened, I may call upon
the gods to destroy my enemy; but the police or the army would be
so much more effective.
From a slightly different perspective, one can use the Parsonian
concept of "real assets" (Parsons
1963) or its Luhmannian version, "symbiotic mechanisms"
(Luhmann 1974), to make the
same point. As long as other function systems have not claimed the
most universal biological factors of human social existence
perception, physical force, sexuality, nourishment, illness, child-rearing,
shelter religion can respecify itself through all of these,
directly or indirectly. But once systems for science, politics,
law, family, economy, health, and education have crystallized around
these, holistic religion, while certainly not irrelevant, will have
to compete with or otherwise influence systemic partners that refer
primarily to one asset or another, but not all of them. Religion,
in such a situation, may well be left with whatever remains, above
all individual and communal integration which points again
to moral codings and "ecstatic" (that is, unusual)
perception; and even in these realms, other systems, such as the
political (above all through the idea of the nation), the legal,
the familial, the medical, and most especially the artistic, offer
a certain amount of competition. In this context, religion becomes
a broadly present type of communication, but one that at the level
of society as a whole has difficulty becoming a clearly convergent
function system like the others because other systems have limited
the possibilities for the technical instrumentalization of religion,
that is, its demonstrable capacity to have immanent effect. The
result is at best a pluralized or multi-centred system: if it were
not for the modern reconstruction of the various religions, there
would be no religious system at all (see Beyer
1997).
This profound ambiguity in the situation of religion in modern
and global society is at the root of why religion and religions
have established a special resonance with the typical problems generated
by a dominance of functional differentiation. It also helps to explain
why the religiously-based responses to those problems are themselves
so ambiguous. It remains in a final section to take a closer look
at the nature of those responses and what they tell us about functionally
differentiated global society more generally.

III
The arguments that I have presented thus far may make it seem that
we are living in an inevitably secularizing society, and that the
ability of religion to respond to the residual problems of functional
differentiation is quite limited. In a sense, that is what I am
suggesting, except that nothing is inevitable, and secularization
does not mean the powerlessness, let alone the disappearance, of
religion. In fact, given religions penchant for claiming to
render access to the meaning of the whole, and that moral codings
still constitute one of the most important secondary codings for
most religions; it would seem to be a very suitable perspective
from which to criticize global society as a whole, and therefore,
as a whole, a society that features a dominance of functional differentiation.
The ambiguity of religion, to use theological language, its tendency
to be "in the world, but not of it", suits this type of
social communication to articulating the problems that seem to be
attendant upon functional differentiation itself. In consequence,
we might expect the representatives of religion to be a prime source
for such criticism. Perhaps just as importantly, we should expect
those critical descriptions that see the problems in the nature
of functional differentiation or technical rationality itself to
take on religious colouring. Because religion takes the paradoxical
perspective of the whole, holistic perspectives will tend to have
a religious look about them.
On the basis of this diagnosis, what is perhaps surprising is that
religious protest of this nature is only somewhat present in contemporary
global society, and not more so. By far the largest part of what
religious institutions and religious people do today is straightforward
religious communication: the recursive reproduction of religion,
more often than not within the functionally systemic framework of
a particular religion. There are, to be sure, emanating from different
religions, various protest movements of the sort the above analysis
suggests. One thinks, for instance, of Christian liberation theology
and militant neo-traditionalist Islam with their characteristic
vilification of capitalism and Western imperialism under such moral
headings as social justice and global arrogance. Catholic bishops
and the pope regularly issue statements lamenting injustice, insecurity,
and environmental degradation as essentially the consequences of
religious and moral failing in global society. The World Council
of Churches has its Justice, Peace, and Integrity of Creation programme
which does something similar (see Beyer
1994 for a more complete analysis). And the list could go on
to include the Dalai Lama, the Maharishi Mahesh Yogi, Soka Gakkai
International, the Unification Church, to name but a few. Taken
together, however, all these manifestations come to very little
when one considers how much protest comes from non-religious sources.
In this regard, beside the critiques emanating from traditional
religious sources, some but only some, of the more "secular"
movements dedicated to addressing the residual problems of global
society also exhibit religious qualities in that they seek a solution
to the problems in dedifferentiation in favour of a "communal"
or "natural" whole. Examples include socialist and communist
movements which have envisioned a classless society usually projected
onto an eschatological future; and ecological movements such as
deep ecology and eco-feminism that seek to retreat to the local
and face-to-face in an effort to escape the deleterious effects
of social differentiation.
With both sorts of protest manifestation, the most important issues
in the present context are not just their presence and even their
frequency. At least as significant, and probably more so, are their
social form and their social effect. The form that they take and
which of them have had the greatest influence in contemporary society
tell us something about religion and about the power of functional
differentiation within global society.
It should surprise no one that the dominant form for these protests
is and has been the social movement. Here we have a social system
that centres precisely around mobilization toward specific goals
(see Ahlemeyer 1989). Social
movements are well suited to protest against the dominant societal
systems because they can to a large extent escape the limitations
of the recursive communication within these systems, and in so doing
highlight and construct the problems that the dominant systems generate
but do not solve. They are well-suited to thematizing that which
the structures of these systems exclude through the selectivity
of their own operations. By comparison to those systems, the possibilities
for social movements are less limited because they can move in anti-structural
ways; and this applies to all societies, not just one dominated
by functional differentiation. Accordingly, the history of new religious
and new political movements is replete with those that appear "new"
by reversing what seems to be taken for granted in the dominant
structures: we have egalitarian movements in stratified societies,
unifying movements in tribal societies, communalizing movements
in functionally differentiated societies, and so forth. Yet, in
all cases, the social movement form also has at least one serious
disadvantage, and that is its instability or even evanescence: a
system characterized by mobilization must either continue to mobilize
or cease to exist as that form of system; much like an interaction
system cannot tolerate too long an interruption of interaction.
For social movements, that means disappearance or the translation
of the movements impulse into the idioms of the dominant systems:
the millenarian and anti-imperial religious movement becomes the
imperial religion; the anti-caste movement becomes another caste;
the radical religious brotherhood founds the next imperial dynasty.
Occasionally, however, social movements are the harbingers of a
more radical shift in societal structures, in dominant forms of
societal differentiation; but this, historically speaking, is rare.
We can, of course, ask whether perhaps contemporary protest movements,
especially religious or quasi-religious ones, contain the seeds
of such rare transformation. That, indirectly, is to ask the question
of efficacy. Which of the protesting movements, including the expressly
religious, has had the most effect; and how have they had that effect?
Even a cursory glance at the anti-systemic movements of the last
century shows that the most effective and powerful ones have been
those that translated their impulses into the idioms of certain
of the dominant function systems, above all the political, which
is to say the modern state. Socialist movements, for instance, translated
into the Soviet Union and the Peoples Republic of China; Islamist
movements have more recently brought us the Islamic Republic of
Iran; non-Western anti-imperial indigenous movements have produced
a host of new nation-states; environmental, labour, and equal rights
movements have seen their concerns translated into a host of laws
and political decisions. Other systems have also been involved to
a lesser degree, notably in the ecological case, the science and
health systems. In many cases, movements have left behind, often
international, non-governmental organizations, many of which address
the residual problems on a regular basis, but have lost most of
their anti-systemicity and their holism in the process.
The result of almost all of the protest movements has been to reproduce
and perhaps even strengthen the dominant function systems. Protest
has produced above all more political, legal, educational, scientific,
health, artistic, and news media communication. Even the capitalist
economic system, often the prime systemic symbol of what is wrong
with modern society, has benefitted through the new range of commodifiable
products and services that protest has engendered. Like the anti-structural
ritual that Victor Turner (1969)
analyzed in his famous work, modern anti-systemic movements, in
order to have an effect, have, if anything, enhanced the systems
that they target. Visions of a better, a utopian world, need to
find the means, the worldly instruments, to realize themselves.
In the current societal context, the most powerful such means take
the form of at least certain of the dominant function systems. That
observation brings back the question of the role of religion.
In a sense, the religious system is the odd one out in this circumstance.
One would be hard-pressed to show that global society has become
a more religious place in the last number of decades. One could
in fact, just as easily argue the reverse. With one or two notable
exceptions, growth in religious communication has happened away
from the movements of protest, in spite of them rather than because
of them. The growth areas in Christianity are among the Pentecostals
and the Evangelical churches, and liberation theology or new Christian
rightism in the United States have had no noticeable effect on that
trend at all. Rather these latter movements have attracted so much
attention precisely because of their politicized character, because
they have taken the form of social movements whose goals have led
them into the political arena. Their relation with the religious
institutions themselves has always been ambiguous (cf. Beyer
1994). Similar observations apply to the growth of Orthodox
Judaism and to politicizing developments in Hinduism and Buddhism.
The possible exceptions appear in Islam, where politicization as
a consequence of protest does seem to have enhanced the power and
presence of the religious institution and its characteristic communication.
Here, however, what is most likely at work is the advantage that
this religion gains through its tradition of using a legal code,
rather than just a moral code, as its main secondary coding (see
Beyer 1998b).
The upshot of the foregoing is that the fate of religion in modern
global society has at least as much, and probably more, to do with
its ability to reproduce itself as a series of religions, subsystems
of a global religious system, as it does with its "prophetic"
capacities. To be sure, the critiques, the protests, the religio-political
movements are a notable feature of our world; and I have argued
elsewhere that they will likely continue precisely because they
offer religion and its representatives a way of having noticeable
public influence (Beyer 1994).
Yet, given the prevalence of function as an organizing principle,
the "application" of religion to residual problems depends
on the continued reproduction and growth of religious institutions
as religious institutions: "applied" religion presumes
"pure" religion at least as much, if not more, than the
reverse. The continued development of a global function system for
religion, in large measure for reasons such as I have analyzed in
this article, is, however, an open question for the future. The
formation and reproduction of religions, self-identified and observed
as such, will probably continue and serve as the resource base for
protest movements against the residual problems of a functionally
differentiated society. Some sort of secularization in the radical
sense of that word seems unlikely, even in Western Europe. Nonetheless,
from a sociological perspective, a global function system for religion
is not necessary; and religion, like morality, could eventually
lose its presence as an observable societal system.
Prof. Peter Beyer, Department of Classics and
Religious Studies
University of Ottawa, 70 Laurier Street East
Ottawa, Ontario, Canada K1N 6N5
pbeyer@aix1.uottawa.ca

|